The Neglected (III): Jacob Burckhardt - Defender of Culture and Prophet of Doom Author(s): Wolfgang J. Mommsen Source: Government and Opposition , AUTUMN 1983, Vol. 18, No. 4 (AUTUMN 1983), pp. 458-475 Published by: Cambridge University Press Stable URL: https://www.jstor.org/stable/44484477 JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org. Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at https://about.jstor.org/terms Cambridge University Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Government and Opposition This content downloaded from 193.84.199.150 on Thu, 02 Mar 2023 06:55:22 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms Wolfgang J. Mommsen The Neglected (III) Jacob Burckhardt - Defender of Culture and Prophet of Doom IN THE STRICTEST MEANING OF THE TERM, JACOB Burckhardt, the eminent historian and widely acclaimed exp on European art, cannot be considered a neglected autho Yet nor does he belong to the mainstream of European polit thinking; he is to be found on the sidelines as a remarkabl but somewhat erratic, figure, representing a unique sort o extreme cultural criticism directed against modernity. Even in his own time Jacob Burckhardt was very much a outsider, to a considerable degree as a result of his own choo ing. Born in Basel in 1818 into a highly respected local fami he remained for most of his life in this beautiful, althoug comparatively remote, Swiss city, rather than seeking accepting academic honours abroad, with the possible except of the five years 1854-58 when he taught history of art the Eidgenössiche Technische Hochschule in Zürich. Repeate offers of chairs at the Universities of Tübingen and Heidelbe were declined and when in 1872 he was offered Ranke's famous chair at the University of Berlin, the foremost chair of history in Germany, he again refused. Likewise, he displayed little ambition as a writer; only a fraction of his oeuvre was published during his lifetime. Admittedly, though, his Die Zeit Constantin des Großen and Kultur der Renaissance in Italien were spectacular successes with a far-reaching impact on further research in these fields and even on the writing of historiography in general. Even so, the most important writings, or at any rate those which were of the greatest interest to the general public, were only published after his death. His most momentous book, the Welthistorische Bertrachtungen , or more correctly, his lectures Über das Studium der Geschichte , were even published contrary to his own intentions. Indeed, it is This content downloaded from 193.84.199.150 on Thu, 02 Mar 2023 06:55:22 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms JACOB BURCKHARDT 459 only since 1982, thanks to Peter Ganz, th factory edition of this most spectacular of This was in fact a series of rather loosely with many additions and notes accompa only to his students and a fairly small cir and academic acquaintances that he con thoughts and as time went by he became to address himself to the general public: only his students who were privy to his thou Jacob Burckhardťs rather remote wa almost exclusively to scholarly work and including numerous trips to see art treasures and the like in Italy and elsewhere in deliberately. Early in his life Burckhardt acted as political editor of the Basel newspa he decided to leave politics alone: Tor m whatever I do, I do as a human being'.2 become entangled in any way whatsoever in Instead, he deliberately opted for a cont which might at first sight be considere sense in which Nietzsche used the term this was not so. His exclusive concern cultural heritage was not a mere refuge, it w politically motivated. Burckhardt acted that historical reflection helps the indivi from the popular prejudices to which e in his own age, enabling him to judge even elevated far above everyday affairs. He hims 'Our contemplative approach is not only le but also a dignified need: for it is tant »Jacob Burckhardt, Über das Studium der Ge 'Weltgeschichtlichen Betrachtungen ' auf Grund der Vor nach den Handschriften herausgegeben von Peter Gan Wolfgang Hardtwig, Geschichtsschreibung zwischen Alt Jacob Burckhardt in seiner Zeit , Göttingen, 1974 and Ha The Historical Imagination in 19th Century Europe , B Also Jörn Rüsen, 'Jacob Burckhardt', in Deutsche Histori Göttingen, 1972. 2 Cf. Karl Löwith, Jacob Burckhardt. Der Mensch in Stuttgart, second ed., 1966, p. 127. Translations by the au This content downloaded from 193.84.199.150 on Thu, 02 Mar 2023 06:55:22 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms 460 GOVERNMENT AND OPPOSITION amidst general servitude and the stream of necessity'.3 cal observation provided a fixed vantage point in the of an ever accelerating process of historical chang as he saw it, had during his lifetime entered the init of what he called the terminal crisis of occidental civi associated with the inevitable decline of the old E culture. LE TERRIBLE ESPRIT DE NOUVEAUTÉ In political terms Jacob Burckhardt was, at any rate at first sight, a radical conservative. In his earlier years he sympathized for a while with the ideas of liberalism. But he soon developed his own brand of conservative thinking which, while it had little in common with conservative party politics, did partially coincide with the conservative positions of his own day. He deliberately stood in the camp of traditional European culture and he was convinced that it could not survive under the conditions of an egalitarian, modern society. Most, if not all, great cultural achievements of the past had been brought about by tiny ruling elites in conjunction with small privileged groups of artists, scholars and writers. The modern age of egalitarianism sounded, so Burckhardt believed, the death knell for the old European culture. Burckhardt's position was in many ways similar to that of Alexis de Tocqueville. Both observed the dechne of the traditional European order with dismay and concern regarding the likely future of freedom and civilization in the approaching age of mass democracy and material civilization. Both were oriented to the social conditions of the pre-revolutionary era, i.e. eighteenth-century Europe with its relatively stable social order and its modest degree of state interference in the life of the average citizen, at least as far as he belonged to the higher orders. Whilst Tocqueville praised the essential role of the intermediate orders in society in providing a maximum of freedom for the individual, Jacob Burckhardt favoured smaller political units and a decentralized European system of powers which allowed a great variety of principalities, 3 Jacob Burckhardt, Gesammelte Werke , Darmstadt, 1956 ff., vol. 4, p. 7. This content downloaded from 193.84.199.150 on Thu, 02 Mar 2023 06:55:22 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms JACOB BURCKHARDT 461 small or large, to live alongside one anothe ground for art, literature and scholarship. If anything, Jacob Burckhardt was ev influenced than Tocqueville by the impact processes of his own day, which he traced Revolution. Tocqueville did not consider t of modern times, which he saw at work in the United States, entirely in negativ as the new democratic principles could be as well as destructive, though perhaps f from the viewpoint of individual freedom was much more of a pessimist. His asses considered to be the revolutionary trends was far more radical. He was of the opinion aries were living in an Age of Revolution ively different from all hitherto known as there was not only historical change the time, often imperceptibly, but change institutions, political or otherwise, and th erating speed.4 In November 1871 Jacob Bu . . . almost everything which we witness in our own cally an Age of Revolution; we are probably on perhaps the second act of this great drama; the decades from 1815 to 1848 have in fact turned out in it. This revolutionary age appears to become which stands out in stark contrast to all known his In Burckhardťs opinion the decisive fa ' le terrible esprit de nouveauté 9 which f had promised to tame, but which by then whole of society and had influenced deepl of all classes of the population.6 The had brought about one principle of decis justifying and willing change allegedly for th More radical than most conservativ Burckhardt saw in this desire for change, * Jacob Burckhardt, Historische Fragmente. Aus dem Emtl Dürr , Stuttgart, 1957, pp. 260 ff. « Ibid., p. 269. « Ibid., p. 275. 7 Ibid., p. 276. Translated by the author. This content downloaded from 193.84.199.150 on Thu, 02 Mar 2023 06:55:22 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms 462 GOVERNMENT AND OPPOSITION was the most distinctive feature of his own age, es a 'blind force' nurtured by a shallow belief in prog propelled by the hope of material gain rather than spiritual or cultural values of any description. On of it, people believed in the possibility of improveme progress through intentional social action; in fact, 'blind desire for change' at work, fuelled by mere mat motives and gaining more and more widespread recog in the course of undermining traditional authority. It because of this fact that, in Burckhardt's view, th Revolution had turned into an accelerating process of which was about to undermine all social differentiations. Burckhardt's extremely critical assessment of his ow and indeed of modern times up to our own, was ar against the backcloth of a highly original interpretatio history of Western culture or, to put it more precisel ticular conception of universal history. Jacob Bur repeatedly stated that he had nothing in common philosophers of history of his own time and his frequ emics against Hegel are a case in point. He objecte attempts at reconstructing the course of world history ine to a guiding principle. 'Such bold anticipation of of world history is bound to fail, because it starts erroneous principle.'8 Hayden White pointed out that this radical stance was based not only on em grounds, notably the argument that usually the gener according to which universal history was reconstruct systematic manner by the philosophers was merely a p of their own personal views, or at any rate the views own time, upon the past. Burckhardt in fact objected varieties of the philosophy of history which attem reconstruct history upon teleological principles of an in particular Hegel's concept of 'progress in the cons of freedom', because he recognized that such philo schemes always contained an element of encouraging by conscious human action, in order eventually to bri an ideal or, at any rate, a better world ana that th fuelled the general desire for change even more.9 s Gesammelte Werke , vol. 4, p. 26. « White, op. cit. y p. 236 f. This content downloaded from 193.84.199.150 on Thu, 02 Mar 2023 06:55:22 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms JACOB BURCKHARDT 463 Burckhardťs objections to this kind of inte extended to his fellow historians as well, National Liberal school of historians who structed history in the light of the present, certain political trends of their own time with an historical aura. All genetic hist genre was repugnant to him, precisely bec to be servile to the predominant fashions knowingly or, more often, unknowingly. Burckhardt^ own frequent statement nothing to do with a systematic approach t of history and that he preferred to give cross-sectional interpretations of particular h have to be taken with a pinch of salt. Even method indulged in the colourful descr phenomena, he in fact wanted to find out factors in the historical process rather than events. He went for the typical, recurrent As a historian he concentrated his end he called 'those things which repeat them the recurrent which correspond with o are therefore understandable to us'.10 He his objective as a historian as 'cultural h marked contrast to the then current noti of history. Cultural historiography was, i a special discipline of history, but an alte of how to reconstruct past reality: 'cul study of a sequence of configurations [ Zus nary history considers the sequence of ev connections.' Likewise, Burckhardt did n primarily in terms of the deeds and ac deliberately shifted the emphasis towards approach which accentuateci the role of m indeed, as a rule, helpless object of histo his control, rather than as being master o this does have a role in his writings as wel 10 Gesammelte Werke, vol. 4, p. 3. u Cf. Jörn Rüsen, *Die Uhr, die die Stunde schlägt. G Kultur bei Jacob Burckhardt', in Historische Prozesse Meier, München, 1978, pp. 189 ff. This content downloaded from 193.84.199.150 on Thu, 02 Mar 2023 06:55:22 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms 464 GOVERNMENT AND OPPOSITION works): 'Our point of departure is the only lasting and, our vantage point, acceptable centre, namely man as an en ing, striving and acting human being as he is and wa always will be.'12 The sequence should be noted, endu (and indeed suffering) is listed first and deliberate ac last! In accordance with this he wanted the word 'happin to be deleted from history, while the opposite notion 'mi tune' ought to be retained. Burckhardt was guided in all t issues by fundamental misgivings as to the notion of the abil of man consciously to determine his own future, on how small a scale, or to reconstruct society in such ways effect genuine progress and a greater degree of freedom the individual. Indeed, he believed that most political ph ophies of his own time, notably liberalism and socia were based upon the false conception of the goodnes man which the prevailing social conditions prevent from experienced in reality. Burckhardt blamed Jean-Jac Rousseau above all for having launched this fundamen false notion as to the original nature of man. His own was essentially a pessimistic one, though, as Theodor Sch pointed out, it proves on closer inspection to be of a dua character. Man has a dual nature: on the one hand he is but a 'bird of prey', on the other he is a spiritual creature and as such is capable of achieving great deeds.13 It is this polar tension in man as a human being which is at the centre of Burckhardt's historical thinking. CULTURE AND THE STATE Indeed, Burckhardt's historiography sought to assess h epochs as being conditioned by the predominance of pa types of human beings. This is most notably the case Griechische Kulturgeschichte , but also in his Kul Renaissance in Italien which in his interpretation w much the creation of a new, extremely individualis of man who excelled in the uninhibited living of his the full and who made full use of all human potent 12 Über das Studium der Geschichte , ed. P. Ganz, p. 226. i3 'Die historischen Krisen im Geschichtsdenken Jacob Burckhard Begegnungen mit der Geschichte , Göttingen, 1962, pp. 142 f. This content downloaded from 193.84.199.150 on Thu, 02 Mar 2023 06:55:22 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms JACOB BURCKHARDT 465 while not hesitating to use force in ord way, if need be, as did the 'men of vio Renaissance period. However, Burckhardt d mind the so-called 'great individuals', the B (who succeeded in imposing their own per tory), but all those who were carriers of a These people are, however, in Burckhardt minorities. Indeed, whether culture, in it can flourish or not depends on whether th viduality is upheld against pressures fr by the state or the religious authorities) o from below, notably the rabble which, greed, would not allow any culture which cratic by nature to emerge or to survive. High culture is, all in all, a rare species It flourishes under particular political, conditions and indeed can attain peaks certain fortunate junctures of history, bu endangered phenomenon prone to suppr of the moment by political, economic, relig of the most diverse kind. It would appe cultural achievements can only come ab of the great drama of world history, par ditional political or religious power structu whilst the resulting power vacuum has no masses who always demand a proper sh which is a corollary to and, to a certain d prerequisite for great art, literature or sc no justification whatsoever for a notion assumes that there is after all progress in slow discontinuous process towards a high humanity and culture. On the contrary, t tells of suffering, of the rise and fall of e and the repeated thoughtless and irrepa cultural achievements of the first order. in the historical process as such; rather events often caused by utterly blind fo the action of 'men of motion' (Bewegungs know about the history of mankind and i nor possess a sound vision of the futur to bring about. History must be considered This content downloaded from 193.84.199.150 on Thu, 02 Mar 2023 06:55:22 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms 466 GOVERNMENT AND OPPOSITION in which constellations occur from time to time which allow men to achieve momentous cultural deeds or to create cultural artefacts, if and because they can afford to elevate themselves above the sphere of mere material deeds. These great cultural achievements constitute a kind of ideal history of mankind which, however, is only present in the minds of a small educated elite which is the main bearer of tradition from one generation to the next. This ideal history of culture stands in stark contrast to general history. It serves as a signpost and provides orientation for all those who want to be human beings in the genuine sense of the word, although they find themselves in the midst of a stream of obligations by which their everyday lives are determined to an ever greater degree. It is at this point that Burckhardt assigns a certain social, or perhaps political, function to the cultural elite, that is to say the so-called Gebildete . In the introduction to Griechische Kulturgeschichte Burckhardt puts this as follows: 'It is the special duty of the educated [des Gebildeten] to acquire as complete a knowledge of the development of culture as possible; this distinguishes him as a conscious human being from the unconscious barbarian.'14 The Gebildete are called upon to act as a counterweight to all those forces in history which operate in favour of the consolidation of the power of the rulers and the further extension of state control which may eventually stifle all individual creative activity and impose rigid doctrinaire views upon the people. Likewise, however, they should resist the rabble who do not care and indeed do not know about culture and aim at levelling all social differentiations regardless of the social costs, material or ideal. In his most famous work, wrongly, but not entirely unjustifiably known by the title World Historical Reflections , Jacob Burckhardt set out to describe the precarious balance between domination and freedom, between the unrestrained rule of individualism and complete state control of all individual conduct. This is the core of his famous, ideal-typical theory of the three great historical forces {Potenzen) of state, religion and culture which forms the backbone of his interpretation of world history and which can rightly be called a philosophy u Gesammelte Werke, vol. 5, p. 15. This content downloaded from 193.84.199.150 on Thu, 02 Mar 2023 06:55:22 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms JACOB BURCKHARDT 467 of history, albeit of a genre different fr Marx, Comte and Spencer. None of these t entirely without the others. Culture in par without a degree of protection by the satisfaction of the primary religious requirem of the population by religious institutions the three Potenzen are reciprocally dep another, whilst nonetheless in irreconcilab another. Burckhardt^ notion of the state or, as w call it in modern terms, of domination is if not pessimistic. He would have nothin the conception of the state as an instituti it is to act as the guardian of certain fund ciples in society or which even embodie as was argued at the time by a whole schoo ophers from Hegel onwards. Nor did Burck with the various attempts to justify, or i origins of the state by reference to natura tual agreement on the part of the ruled in In a rather naturalistic vein he maintaine far as we can see violence is always f constituted by power and not by whate principles to which recourse may be take domination in one way or another. In the is always evil, whoever is exercising it. It facto insatiable, hence as such unhappy an to make others unhappy as well.'15 The propensity to extend its control over an e human affairs and at the same time a passi which may prove irresistible if it is no of the other two primary forces in world conceded that in modern times a certain moderation in the brutal nature of state power had been achieved, as often happened in the later stages of cultural development, but he stuck rigidly to the opinion that the state has no function in the sphere of morality. It was not the duty of the state to impose moral principles upon society; this was entirely up to the latter. is Über das Studium der Geschichtet ed. Ganz, p. 257. This content downloaded from 193.84.199.150 on Thu, 02 Mar 2023 06:55:22 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms 468 GOVERNMENT AND OPPOSITION Burckhardt also strongly objected to those notions attributed to the state, and in particular to the moder state, a cultural mission of whatever kind. He was qu spoken about this: 'On the contrary, in the first p nation wants power above all. . . one wishes to be something great and thereby reveals that power is th and culture at best a secondary objective.' 16 There one relative justification for state power and even fo power status, namely 'the necessity of achieving great ob in foreign affairs, the preservation and protection of which would otherwise perish and the promotion of sections of the people, themselves given to passivity. from the point of view of culture, not the great but t state, like those to be found in the system of city st signorie in Renaissance Italy or in eighteenth-century Ger were infinitely preferable. A decentralized exercise o was an ideal figuration for the growth of sublime culture The function of religion in history was asse Burckhardt with even more detachment and coolness of attitude. The great world religions undoubtedly catered for the religious needs of the people, known in all ages and by all peoples, but in doing so they tended to petrify the original religious messages by gradually creating powerful religious institutions which largely monopolized the teaching of religious doctrine and the ways of achieving salvation, thereby becoming serious rivals to the state. The institutionalization of religious doctrine, which kept the latter alive long after the original religious fervour had evaporated, was tantamount to stifling all cultural growth again, if not held in check by the state, or by the forces of society in its own right. While state and religion are static elements in the great drama of world history, permanently attempting to extend their sway over their peoples by all the means at their disposal and, if necessary, eliminating ail individual spheres of activity, culture is a dynamic element. 'Its impact uppn both state and religion is one of continuous modification and decomposition except under conditions when they have subjected culture totally to their will and made it subservient to their own i« Gesammelte Werke , vol. 4, p. 70. n Ibid., p. 24. This content downloaded from 193.84.199.150 on Thu, 02 Mar 2023 06:55:22 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms JACOB BURCKHARDT 469 objectives.' This led Burckhardt to emphasize always have to be a strict dividing line betwe ciety; for, at least in its outward form, soc culture against the other two Potenzen. Ind was rather modern in that he did include the sp life and economic production in his notion of which on close examination is by no means mea a lofty matter exclusively concerned with art scholarship; rather, it encompasses the whole of m It is the spontaneity of human action and n principles by which culture is defined, at leas material culture, as it were, creates a certain 'sp which, being accumulated over the centuries, ground for all those forms of human activity becomes conscious of himself as a spiritual stage is reached, however, this most sublime activity becomes a historical force in itself: 6 We einmal seiner selbst bewußt geworden, bildet seine Welt weiter.' ls At this juncture Burckhardt is far closer to himself was aware. Indeed, his naturalistic app cal reality in many ways reflects the classical towards history as a force not dissimilar to governed by fate and undisclosed laws rather will and human action. The great cultural ach acquire a semi-eternal status inasmuch as t become part and parcel of the cultural heri or a group of peoples, are ultimately creation spirit. Even the destructive forces which inevit empires and religious institutions which seem built for eternity originate from this most s of human activity. It is apparent from this t Burckhardt was not such a rigid conservative t appear from his commentaries concerning politics in his own time. It should be noted any such dynamic activity leading to social cha manifestations, whilst being the source of su scholarly achievements, is the province of elites who enjoy a markedly privileged sta »8 Gesammelte Werke , vol. 4, p. 44. This content downloaded from 193.84.199.150 on Thu, 02 Mar 2023 06:55:22 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms 470 GOVERNMENT AND OPPOSITION materially and otherwise, while the common people h furnish the means of subsistence for them. Burckhardt inclined to think that the smaller and the more elevated from everyday life these elites were, the more they achieved. Hence, culture requires social conditions of a very specific nature. These elite groups can never be upheld against the many without invoking state authority or religious tradition in order to justify a hierarchical order in society which gives them a privileged status. Culture is, therefore in a way, just as dependent upon the state as an agency providing protection against outside forces or internal convulsions and upon religion as a source of traditionalist legitimation, as they, in turn, are dependent upon society and culture. Everything depends, therefore, upon whether a reasonable balance exists between these elements; only under such conditions can genuine culture really thrive for any long period and create lasting cultural artefacts. The Greek polis would appear to have been one such fortunate configuration and the Italian Renaissance another. Possibly, the decentralized system of a plurality of smaller powers in Central Europe, with but a fictitious central authority during the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries, was another, though perhaps not quite as propitious for the cultivation of an individualist culture. But quite apart from that, a relative balance between the three key forces of history would appear to be essential for culture to flourish and furthermore for the survival of any given social system as such. It is historically possible for one of the three forces (Potenzen) to gain the upper hand over the other two, or perhaps for two of them jointly to dominate the third. For example, the state may take over complete control of religion, or subject culture entirely to its own interests. If this happens, it may be irretrievably lost as an independent variable in the unending stream of the historical process. This would be tantamount to condemning the respective social system to slow but certain petrification. More often than not, culture was made totally subservient to state power, thereby losing its inherent quality of being a source of dynamic change, let alone great cultural achievement. (It is difficult nowadays not to think of the social systems within the Soviet bloc which conform almost exactly to the criteria just mentioned.) This content downloaded from 193.84.199.150 on Thu, 02 Mar 2023 06:55:22 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms JACOB BURCKHARDT 471 According to Burckhardt it is more likely t between the three Potenzen may trigger o respective social system which may, accordi stances, not only lead to its rapid destruc other, adjacent historical formations into it all be doomed to eventual death due to a serie convulsions. Indeed, in such times the pro change accelerates. Social formations whic up gradually over decades or even centuries m tally altered or destroyed within months or states or established religions may either co course of such 'historical crises', or enhan beyond what had been thought possible b least in its more sublime variations, is alway badly if not become lost altogether. THE THEORY OF HISTORICAL CHANGE It is this theory of historical change which provides of departure for Burckhardt's judgments on the po social developments of his own age. Burckhardt w convinced that since the rise of the modern industr and the French Revolution, the precarious balan three Potenzen had been severely disturbed. Th had been a necessary prerequisite for the emergenc ditional European culture as a most sublime exp man's spiritual activity. The impact of the French R and of the doctrines of liberalism and democracy so deep that the all-important dividing line betw and society (the latter being the material embo culture) was about to be progressively eroded. U conditions of universal or at any rate popular suffra demands upon the state to fulfil the material ne people, rather than to stick to its traditional role a of the social order externally and internally, ha too strong to be resisted any longer. This, however, n an extension of state control over society in almost of life. In Burckhardt's opinion this development would do neither of them any good. On the one hand it would result in a mushrooming of state power, through which all individual initiative This content downloaded from 193.84.199.150 on Thu, 02 Mar 2023 06:55:22 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms 472 GOVERNMENT AND OPPOSITION would gradually be stifled, on the other hand govern power would become more and more subservient to th of the masses. The eventual outcome would be, he the rise of caesaristic regimes as the obvious form of a compatible with universal suffrage. The caesaristic gre state of the future would have little patience with th heritage of its predecessors, nor would it any longer sufficient shelter for those social groups primarily in in the arts and the sciences. The rise of modern nation was another factor which worked in the same direction. It gave additional stimuli to the rise of the omnipotent state which subjects society entirely to its objectives. Indeed, from the start, Burckhardt was disillusioned with the nationalist doctrine of his age, with its liberal just as much as with its more conservative variation. Burckhardťs deep-seated worries were further intensified by his analysis of the emerging industrial system. On the whole he assessed its momentous consequences for the modern world remarkably correctly. It was about to change fundamentally the condition of life for everybody, but he had ht tie to say in its favour. Rather, he was appalled by the impact of the new industrial spirit upon the cultural heritage of Europe. With the greatest concern he observed that railways and industry were making deep inroads daily into what could be considered the European cultural heritage; with considerable fervour, reminiscent of present-day ecological debates, he deplored that the great historical metropolises of Europe were about to be defaced by railways, bridges, factories and opulent but tasteless buildings on an ever grander scale. He certainly welcomed the foundation of new museums everywhere and the great efforts being made by the new bourgeoisie, as well as by the aristocracy, to collect art treasures, a process which was facilitated by the enormous wealth created by industrial capitalism, partly because it was so unevenly spread amongst the population. But he nonetheless complained bitterly about the almost daily loss or defacement of important artefacts of the culture of the past. During his second visit to London in 1879 Burckhardt filled his diary with many notes to this effect; he regretted that the face of London was being This content downloaded from 193.84.199.150 on Thu, 02 Mar 2023 06:55:22 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms JACOB BURCKHARDT 473 destroyed by more and more new, ugly railw preposterous buildings.19 This attitude was more than mere sentiment the past. Burckhardt was fully aware that t of historical monuments or the gradual def historical aspect, of the urban environment i bound to have unfortunate repercussions on traditional cultural ideas as such. This was only from an aesthetic point of view, but also and, in a way, on Uberai grounds; the cultu in Burckhardťs view the breeding ground f creative initiatives might grow which, in turn impetus for the rise of new forms of soci expression and, perhaps, for the rise of new h tions. What Burckhardt was concerned about w finahty of what he saw going on; the driving the new industriahzation appeared to be b and irreversible as they were propelled, in by a desire for material gain and progress in the of the masses. It was at this very juncture th high conservatism converged with extreme lef the nature of the capitalist system which alle mankind to a new servitude. The people, or at whelming majority of them, were not, howev at all. On the other hand, Burckhardt anticip for culture which might originate from anti-c Rather gloomily he remarked: 'You cannot a tyranny will be exercised over the spirit und that erudition is a clandestine ally of capit be annihilated.'20 Burckhardt was fairly sure that the twin forces and industriahzation were bound to lead to an era of 'national wars and deadly international competition'.21 This in turn would encourage the rise of militarism as the most effective 19 Cf. Werner Kaegi, 'Europäische Horizonte im Denken Jacob Burckhardts', Drei Studien , Basel, 1962, pp. 13 ff. 20 Löwith, op. cit., p. 156. 21 Historische Fragmente , p. 278. This content downloaded from 193.84.199.150 on Thu, 02 Mar 2023 06:55:22 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms 474 GOVERNMENT AND OPPOSITION form of mobilizing the political and physical power of engaged in political and economic rivalry or even open with each other. Soon the rulers would discover the ad of a militaristic organization of society from the vie of the power interest of the caesarist state which in seemed to be the obvious answer to the needs of In prophetic visions Burckhardt sketched the outlines he thought was bound to come sooner or later. In Ap he wrote to Heinrich von Preen: The fate of the workers will perhaps be most conspicuous; I hav boding which may sound silly right now, but which nonetheles get out of my mind: the military state is bound to become an in on a grand scale. The agglomerations of men in the huge industr shops must not be left forever to their misery and their greed measure of misery, carefully controlled, begun and ended w of drums, with advancement and in uniform - it is this that is bound to come.22 This and other similar prophetic statements have righ considered as a forecast, however vaeue, of the ris totalitarian state and, in particular, Fascism. I Burckhardt's concern with the amorphous structur modern state which has somehow swallowed society, itself becoming prey to nationalism and demands greater welfare provisions, touched a sore point. Sinc Talmon and many others have elaborated upon m same point, namely that an unstructured society in w individuals have no independent standing and no inter institutions to fall back on in case of necessity, tend rise to despotic rule, as the balance of the social force is a necessary prerequisite for free societies, is lost. It has to be admitted, however, that Burckhardt overemphasized the authoritarian and indeed the ca trends of his own time and much the same can pe said of his rather negative assessment of modern indu He was so much of an anti-modernist that he sometimes t to exaggerate his observations to a more than tolerabl On the other hand, he was always careful to prese in a cautious and indeed merely impressionistic mann « Cf. Jacob Burckhardt, Briefe, ed. M. Burckhardt, Bremen, 1965, April, 1872). This content downloaded from 193.84.199.150 on Thu, 02 Mar 2023 06:55:22 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms JACOB BURCKHARDT 475 forecast of the caesaristic super-state never region; nor were his forebodings of despo distant future intended to be more than ind certain trends of post-revolutionary Europ lighted, trends which might assert themse reality only if no counteracting factors i Burckhardt offered were impressionistic, analyses which, however tentatively they w nonetheless threw and still throw light on key society. They were arrived at by a careful an tory and opened up possible alleys for inter present and the future alike. Burckhardt himself was deeply pessimistic of European civilization as he knew it. 'I d thing of the future', he wrote as early as 18 that we will still be granted a few fairly similar to Roman antiquity under the emper hope that he still had, he placed on a nearly from the predominant trends of his own time a keep knowledge about the old European cu the public or, at any rate, among the erudite the standard-bearers of aestheticism, cult consciousness. Burckhardt defended this o defensive yet at the same time remarkably p 'We may all perish, but at least I want to ch the interest for which I am to perish, name Old Europe.'24 This was perhaps not quite to take as Burckhardt would have had hi believe.25 If anything could help, he thought the study of art and literature and history in from the predominant fashions of his age. A might emerge in which the spirit of European c and indeed hidden in aesthetic artefacts and s might provide once again the fertile ground by which the historical process might be given able direction. 23 Briefe, ed. M. Burckhardt, vol. III, p. 112. 24 Ibid., p. 146 (5 March 1846). 25 A few lines later Burckhardt speaks of 'reconstruction the crisis is over', as his and his partner's destiny. This content downloaded from 193.84.199.150 on Thu, 02 Mar 2023 06:55:22 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms